METAPHYSICS  .  COSMOLOGY  .  TRADITION  .  SYMBOLISM
  Studies in Comparative Religion
The First English Journal on Traditional Studies - established 1963
 
Skip Navigation Links
   Home
Authors
Archive
Book Review
Browse
Journal Information
Future Issues
Free Subscription
Purchase Copies
Help



For Articles -
Click on underlined term for definition from



Printed Editions
Available for Purchase


Newest Commemorative
Annual Editions:


A special web site:

To visit a special web site, "Frithjof Schuon Archive," dedicated to featured Studies contributor Frithjof Schuon, click here.

 
Article Printer Friendly Printer Friendly 
Click to learn about adding or editing pop-up defintions.

Correspondence

Source: Studies in Comparative Religion, Vol. 2, No. 3. (Summer, 1968) © World Wisdom, Inc.
www.studiesincomparativereligion.com


Sir,

Concerning the recent article by Philip Sherrard, on "Man and the presence of Evil in Christian and Platonic Doctrine," there are certain important matters of principle, which I think demand attention. Firstly, there is his assertion of a contradiction between the Platonic idea of emanation and the Christian idea of creation. Now if this supposed contradiction is admissible, it could only be with regard to a most narrow and scholastic kind of Platonism. In itself, however, it will be found to be quite unreal, as soon as all the essential doctrine is taken into account. Most important in this connection is that of the Pralayas, represented in Hinduism as the "day" and "night" of Brahman. Properly understood, this completely does away with the contradiction between the idea of God as free and purely transcenda­ent, and God as emanating the manifest under sheer necessity. Subject to this doctrine, there is no question of a creation existing as it were "in parallel" with God. Periodically, it vanishes in its entirety, (the Apocatastasis, in Christian terms) to leave God "all in all," but for as long as it exists, it does so according to all the necessity asserted by the Platonists.

This supra-temporal periodic appearance and disappearance of ever-different creations gives to both sides all they require. To the Christian side, it ensures the freedom of God before the complete contingency of the creation, and to the Platonist side, it admits of the whole ontological rigour by which the creation exists, in so far as it does exist. The periodic cessation of the creation, by the way, was by no means unknown to the classical Platonists, as it was taught in the Orphic Tradition. According to Erigena, the four divisions of Being were between the Untreated, creating and not creating, and the created, creating and not creating likewise. The first pair constitutes the metaphysical reason for the universal Substance and Essence: Substance exists because God is eternally non-creative (the "night" of Brahman), and Essence because He is eternally creative under the opposite aspect (the "day" of Brahman). The fact that these two aspects are separate for us at all is due only to the conditions of our own manifest state, and in no way to that of God.

Secondly, the assumption that Platonism does not admit of anything supreme over intellect flies in the face of the express teachings of both Plotinus (Enn. III, tract. viii) and Proclus. In dealing with all the inward powers of the soul, Proclus places the power of the pure intellect subordinate to the highest of all. The latter, he asserts, is "above intellect," and that whoever energises according to it "will understand how the Gods alone ineffably know all things, according to the one of themselves." (On Providence and Fate, 24).

Finally, it must be made clear that the ideas of emanation and creation are in no sense equal alternatives, as would appear from the above article. While both have their own truth, the idea of creation relates to an altogether more relative point of view than that of emanation; it considers things from the substantive pole, in which created forms really do appear as if out of nothing, like images on a screen. But this obviously cannot conflict with the idea of emanation, which simply gives expression to the point of view of the Principle itself. (The other idea, that the One does not admit of complexity, is simply incredible, in view of the fact that the Orphic-Platonic pantheon is developed on the trinitarian principle through and through).

Although these questions can only be dealt with in summary fashion in this space, there is still one more metaphysical principle which must absolutely conclude the present issue, and that is the "irreversibility" of all relationships between the Infinite and the finite. Briefly, this means that while the Infinite exists for the finite being, the latter does not exist at all for the Infinite. (Also called the One, or the Godhead). This is because even the greatest finite being is still as much "zero" in relation to the Infinite as the least, or otherwise the Infinite could be approached in finite steps, and so not be itself. Consequently, no property of the finite could possibly affect the Infinite as such, as its very existence does not.

Even though this may sound dogmatic to some readers, I would like it to be appreciated that the purpose of these indications is only to help make it understood that true metaphysics admits no real contradictions when complete principles are possessed.

In the second part of the same article, the same desire to find contradictions leads to yet other important doctrinal questions, but which can still be settled by reference to the traditional knowledge available to us. After an account as to how and why evil is inevitable according to Platonic theory, there follows the illogical (and unscriptural) conclusion that, if evil really was inevitable, man could have no responsibility for any of his misdeeds. This involves firstly the comical fallacy according to which a criminal might try to justify his crime on the grounds that statistics showed that a number of similar crimes must have been committed by that time, anyway; or a murderer, on the grounds that the victim would have died sooner or later in any case! At the same time, the Gospels plainly teach the inevitability of evil also, as in "It is impossible but that offences must come," while adding: "but woe unto him through whom they come!" (Lk. 17 v. 1). Thus the necessity of evil in general is just as Christian a concept as individual responsibility, (See also Rom. 9, vv. 15-24), and to this, Platonism simply supplies the necessary background of theory.

The next question arises where it is asserted that Christian doctrine teaches that a created world free from evil is possible, and was so intended from the beginning; that Adam of his own free choice fell from it, and that Christ on earth actually achieved it. The trouble here is a basic defect in terminology: in discussing the "evil" nature of matter, or finitude, Mr. Sherrard completely ignores the fact that in this instance "evil" must not be understood in its usual human sense. If it is so understood, there will certainly be no difficulty in making it seem against commonsense to ascribe such a quality to creation as such. However, the essential reality of evil (albeit negative) lies in the separation from God which creation or manifestaa­tion necessarily involves. In this, all creation is ontologically "evil" in itself, no matter how free it may be from everything usually denoted by this word. This truth is also implicit in Christ's reply "Why callest thou me good? There is none good but one, that is, God." (Mt. 19, v.17). Of these two senses of the word evil, it is the ontological one which must be given precedence here, because it contains the other, and is self-sufficing; while this order of evil prevails uncompensated, the absence or removal of what is only humanly evil has no spiritual importance.

Another misleading word here is that of "freedom," which is used purely in its popular sense, as the ability to do either right or wrong equally; thus evil is said to begin through a misuse of Adam's freedom. When used in this sense, however, "freedom" really means "freedom of indifference," which would certainly be opposed to necessity, were it not that this kind of freedom can belong only to God, and never to any finite being. Actually, the only generally valid definition of freedom is "absence of constraint," implying the possession of a degree of unity which contains, rather than confronts, all otherness. In this case, the "freedom" to reject God (Unity itself) must really mean no more than the possibility of losing freedom. But this purely negative possibility, being just the opposite of true freedom, Adam's fall comes about by reason of the presence in him of this same ontological "evil" which characterises all creation. (Correlatively, one might also ask who would count the possibility of losing money as a kind of wealth?) If Adam had been absolutely free, he could never have fallen, but in that case he would have been God; as it was, he fell because of the one respect in which he was not free. Thus the idea of freedom can only be found to contradict the principle of necessity when it is understood in its popular and quite erroneous sense.

Furthermore, it cannot be maintained, as it was in this article, that Christian doctrine implies that the creature cannot or does not participate generically in Being. The short answer to any such statement would be that any entity which did not participate in Being would simply be a non-entity, a sheer illusion. The principle of Being is essentially unique, whence no real existence can have any sufficient reason in anything else. This fact can easily be overlooked when the principle of creation, with its implied "independence," in the creature is believed to be metaphysically on the same level as that of emanation. But in reality, the creationist point of view is too partial and relative in relation to that of emanation to be able to lend any validity to the independence of the creature.

Lastly, to say that it is man's destiny to share God's uncreated life without becoma­ing other than what he "essentially" is, is perfectly true in itself, but quite false if the essence of human nature is identified with man's mortal and limitative condia­tions, as it so often is. Man's essence resides in God, whose "image" he bears, and there is no orthodox doctrine which teaches that his actual state adds anything to this. Thus the more he sheds the forms of his finitude, the more he becomes truly himself, because he only came to be in his actual mortal state through a profound obscuration of his real essence in the first place, as both the Bible and Platonic theory teach in their own ways. Allied to this, the transposition of time, or tempora­ality, into eternity is also unintelligible, since time contributes nothing to manifestaa­tion except the greater part of its limitations.

I am only too aware that all these points do not seem to allow much room to balance with an appreciation of the merits of the article in question, which are certa­ainly not to be denied. But if this addition to the foregoing should seem over-long, I only hope that the inherent interest attaching to these principles brought into consideration by Mr. Sherrard will atone for it to some extent.

Coventry, 25.6.68.

R. BOLTON.


PDF of Article

Click View PDF to view.
View PDF

Home | Authors | Archive | Book Review | Browse | Journal Information | Future Issues | Free Subscription | Purchase Copies | Help | Sitemap |
This site is best viewed 1024 x 768
Copyright © 2007